* This is the second part of a three part “Problematica” on Stephen Jay Gould and punctuated equilibria. You can find Part 1 here, and Part 3 here. In Part 1, Max introduced a historical puzzle: how did an adaptationist with a nose for biological improvement formulate a theory (punctuated equilibria) that would come to be associated with a radically different view of evolution? In the present part, Max considers punctuated equilibria itself and argues that it is easy to square with a broadly adaptationist and progressivist view of evolution. Indeed that was precisely what Gould did, for a while…
In The Structure of Evolutionary Theory, Stephen Jay Gould devotes about 300 pages to punctuated equilibria (PE), spanning a single sprawling chapter. He justifies the indulgence by claiming that PE permits species-level selection by individuating species in geological time. So, PE is foundational to the hierarchical expansion of evolutionary theory that is the book’s main theme. But this does not exhaust PE’s importance for Gould, since the idea also functions as a “coordinating centerpiece… for a larger and coherent set of mostly iconoclastic concerns [in evolutionary theory and the history of life]” (Gould 2002, 37). One of these is a critique of “Darwinian functionalism,” which amounts to a criticism of the idea that all evolutionary phenomena flow from the operation of natural selection in local populations. Another is an assault on the notion that progress supplies an important vector in the history of life. (Those of you who have read the first part of this essay will have noticed that these themes represent near-perfect inversions of the commitments Gould held as a young researcher.)
The puzzle I will try to solve in the third and final part of this essay is how PE came to play this coordinating role, given that Gould remained committed to adaptationism and a broadly progressive view of life’s history even after the publication of “Punctuated equilibria: an alternative to phyletic gradualism” (1972). Yet before we come to this we must ask another question: why did the publication of PE in 1972 fail to rouse Gould from his dogmatic slumber? If PE was pregnant with major implications for evolutionary theory, why did Eldredge and Gould fail to bring them out? In short, how did the guy described in Part 1 of this essay weather the publication of PE with his basic view of evolution mostly intact?
The answer is that nothing in the original articulation of PE forced Gould to abandon either his adaptationism or his confidence that progress supplies an overarching theme in the history of life. So he didn’t—at least not right away. His views would shift considerably in the mid-1970s, and by 1980 would resemble those expressed in Structure. But that leaves the first half of the decade to make sense of. This was a period of relative stasis, at least as regards Gould’s basic ideas about evolution, which was terminated by an abrupt shift. The present part of this essay seeks to come to grips with the stasis; Part 3 concerns the punctuation.
Because David Sepkoski has already described the origin of PE in Rereading the Fossil Record (Chapter 5), I will mostly ignore this history here. Instead, I am going to focus on Eldredge and Gould’s discussion of trends, which they would later advance as the basis of a new view of macroevolution compelling a hierarchical revision of evolutionary theory. What I want to show is the surprising extent to which this treatment meshed with Gould’s other ideas about evolution, in particular, his commitment to the importance of biological improvement driven by natural selection.*
[* The section of “Punctuated Equilibria” dealing with trends was written by Eldredge, but this is irrelevant to my argument. What matters is that Gould signed off on it, and that this involved no reworking of his basic ideas about evolution or the goals of evolutionary paleontology.]
Punctuated equilibria
To begin, a primer. PE is based on a model of speciation developed by Ernst Mayr, in which a (typically small) population becomes isolated from a source population at the periphery of its range. After a period of isolation the “peripheral isolate” loses its ability to interbreed with the source population, at which point it graduates to the rank of a new species. Mayr proposed that these isolates are good candidates to undergo rapid evolution owing to their small size and likely habitation in new environments. They are also more likely than source populations to incubate evolutionary novelties, including entirely new structures and ways of life.
This is why. During the normal run of a species’ existence, its genes form a tightly coadapted bundle, precluding extensive reworking of the gene pool. During speciation, by contrast, a reduction in population size exposes homozygotes to selection and more generally “produce[s] a sudden change of the genetic environment of most loci” (Mayr 1954, 170). At this point all hell breaks loose, genetically speaking, and this permits the population to “pass from one well integrated and rather conservative condition… to another” (172). It is the genetic equivalent of moving from Louis XVI to Napoleon via the Terror. It is how biological Ancien Régimes fall, and are replaced by newer and, perhaps, better ones.
What Eldredge and Gould asked was what we should expect to see in sedimentary successions if this model is correct. Their answer is that we should expect a pattern of morphological stasis (corresponding to the stratigraphic range of the source population) punctuated by rapid change (corresponding to the reinvasion of a formerly isolated peripheral offshoot, say). This will generate an apparently gappy record lacking smooth morphological transitions. But if the model is correct, these gaps are artifacts of the speciation process itself. The intermediate forms exist(ed), they just don’t exist where a naive observer would expect to find them (and perhaps because of the small size of peripheral isolates they are less likely to be preserved as fossils).* By contrast, the morphological stability of the source population is not an artifact. Instead, it is evidence that something was preventing the population from changing: in Mayr’s terminology, the “homeostasis” of coadapted gene pools.
[* Mayr himself makes this point in his (1954): “It seems to me that many puzzling phenomena, particularly those that concern paleontologists, are elucidated by a consideration of [peripherally isolated] populations. This concerns primarily the phenomena of unequal (and particularly rapid) evolutionary rates, breaks in evolutionary sequences and apparent saltations, and finally the origin of new ‘types’” (175).]
So far there is nothing in this treatment to shake the foundations of evolutionary theory. As one reviewer of Models in Paleobiology put it, the proposal “will sound novel only to earth scientists who have not read anything in 20 years[!]” (This is somewhat uncharitable since Eldredge and Gould make much of the ubiquity of morphological stasis, and this is not cribbed from Mayr.) But Eldredge and Gould stake a claim to novelty in their discussion of large-scale evolutionary trends. They begin with a puzzle. Grant that species spend the majority of their histories in morphological stasis. How then are paleontologists to explain the existence of long-term directional changes in higher taxa? Slow and steady evolution in lineages will not do the trick, since on this view most change is cramped into relatively infrequent speciation events separating a whole lotta nothing. Perhaps natural selection acts to shift morphology in the same direction whenever new species happen to arise, but this seems improbable. Instead, Eldredge and Gould
envision multiple ‘explorations’ or ‘experimentations’ (see Schaeffer 1965)—i.e., invasions, on a stochastic basis, of new environments by peripheral isolates. There is nothing inherently directional about these invasions. However, a subset of these new environments might, in the context of inherited [sic] genetic constitution in the ancestral components of the lineage, lead to a new and improved efficiency. Improvement would be consistently greater within this hypothetical subset of local conditions that a population might invade. The overall effect would then be one of net, apparently directional change: but as with the case of selection upon mutations, the initial variation would be stochastic with respect to this change.
Basically, if speciation is random with respect to the direction of an ongoing trend, and if there is some reason that species varying in the direction of the trend are likely to do better than those varying in another direction, then a process of differential survival among incipient species will drive the trend forward, generating directional change.
If the expression “new and improved efficiency” made your ears tingle, then I’ve done my job. As you may have guessed, I’m going to make a big deal out of this in the next section. First, though, I want to glance ahead to 1977, when the sequel to “Punctuated Equilibria: An Alternative to Phyletic Gradualism” appeared. Titled “Punctuated Equilibria: The Tempo and Mode of Evolution Reconsidered,” it presents the same basic story about trends, with random speciation (analogous to mutation) followed by the non-random success of a subset of speciations (natural selection). There is one big difference, however. In the new paper, the emphasis falls on the “decoupling” of micro- and macroevolution via punctuated equilibria, and its implication for the explanation of general patterns in the history of life. In this formulation, “speciation interposes itself as an intermediate level between macroevolutionary trends and evolutionary events within populations.” It follows, Gould and Eldredge claim, that the explanation of macroevolutionary trends must involve processes other than those active in local populations: in particular, processes that operate on populations of species.
A full discussion of this reimagining of PE must await the third part of this essay. The point of raising it here is simply to observe that claims of “decoupling” are not simply a restatement of the view given in Eldredge and Gould (1972). The idea that macroevolution is decoupled from microevolution, and that major features in the history of life owe to an irreducible domain of macroevolutionary causes, was an addition to what Eldredge had written in 1972. Perhaps it was implicit in the original treatment, but anyway it was not highlighted, and probably it was not even recognized. I suspect it was not recognized because in order to embrace decoupling, Eldredge and especially Gould had to abandon certain ideas that they were not keen to give up on in 1972. This took an external stimulus. Regardless, the point for now is that nothing in the logic of PE itself forced Eldredge or Gould to rethink the centrality of adaptation and progress in the history of life. So they didn't, until they had to.
Punctuation and progress
To see why this is the case, we need to return to their original discussion of evolutionary trends.
Recall that for Eldredge and Gould, speciation involves the adaptation of an isolated segment of a population to novel environmental conditions. By itself, this is not expected to produce directional trends in higher taxa. But imagine that some isolates find themselves in environments to which they are especially well-fitted, despite having evolved to live in rather different environments (the phenomenon of preadaptation). Then we can expect, as George Simpson puts it in Tempo and Mode in Evolution, that “[such] groups [will be] subjected to strong selection pressure and [will] evolve rapidly in the further direction of adaptation to the new [conditions]” (123). What Eldredge and Gould propose is that this process will sometimes produce “net, apparently directional change” in a group of lineages. But when, exactly? In their words: when a subset of environments exist whose invasion yields “new and improved efficiency,” permitting certain isolates to survive when so many others perish.
In all this adaptation is the key consideration. But not all adaptations are created equal. According to an old paleontological adage, adaptive specialization is the enemy of evolutionary progress. On this view, specialized lineages sacrifice evolutionary plasticity for short term adaptive gains. The result is the improvement of some organs at the expense of others, leading to what Julian Huxley calls “limiting” or “one-sided” improvement (Huxley 1942, 564). (Think of a parasite, which becomes better at its craft by shedding certain organs.) However, there also exist adaptations that contribute to “raising [the] upper level of all-round functional efficiency.” These adaptations are the stuff of open-ended evolutionary progress. They are the source, ultimately, of higher taxa representing new grades of functional organization. In a word, they are exactly the kind of adaptations that are likely to be incorporated into large-scale evolutionary trends.
Are these non-limiting adaptations what Eldredge and Gould have in mind when they speak about “new and improved efficiency”? There are at least two reasons to think so. First, Eldredge and Gould cite Bobb Schaeffer in connection with their concept of “‘explorations’ or ‘experimentations’ (see Schaeffer 1965)—i.e., invasions, on a stochastic basis, of new environments by peripheral isolates.” This matters because Schaeffer’s 1965 paper is about “[the] role of experimentation in the origin of higher levels of organization,” which Schaeffer understands, following Huxley, as grades of increasing functional efficiency. Schaeffer was a paleontologist at the American Museum and a professor at Columbia University, where Eldredge and Gould were graduate students in the 1960s. They must have known that his concept of experimentation involves the “trying out” of sets of character until (so to speak) one of them achieves an overall improvement. As Schaeffer writes, “Each successful [character] combination must be adapted to a particular ecological niche, but some combinations may also represent improved solutions to functional problems common to many different niches.” Not all adaptations are created equal.*
[* We should be wary of over-interpreting a single citation, but if the analogy of speciation to “experimentation” is taken at all seriously, then successful “experiments” will be those that experience a broad and non-limiting kind of adaptive improvement.]
The second reason is a conceptual one. If all speciation involves adaptation to local conditions, then Eldredge and Gould cannot specify the subset of a directional trend by gesturing at adaptation or “improvement” as such. They must have a special kind of improvement in mind, like an increase in overall efficiency as opposed to the refinement of a narrow functional capacity. And as luck would have it, there is some textual evidence that this is the case. In a book chapter published in 1977, Gould remarks that many nineteenth century paleontologists rejected natural selection because it offered no toehold for a belief in progress (a dubious historical claim on Gould’s part). These paleontologists were right, Gould claims: natural selection operating within populations generates no overall directionality, only a toing and froing of population in response to shifting local exigencies. However, “once we discard the shackles of phyletic gradualism as an explanation for ‘trends’, we can see that the operation of natural selection in evolutionary time can yield direction” (Gould 1977, 22). His explanation follows Eldredge and Gould (1972), but is more explicit at key points:
The primary events of speciation yield no direction, for they only adapt populations to local environments. But all speciations do not have an equal phyletic longevity or an equal opportunity for further speciation. Trends represent the differential success of subsets from a random spectrum of speciations. Improved biomechanical efficiency, for example, represents one pathway to adaptation in local environments. The species that follow this path—rather than the acquisition of a limiting, morphological specialization—might form the subset of a directional trend. (Gould 1977, 22, emphases added)
Admittedly, Gould writes “for example,” which indicates that improved biomechanical efficiency isn’t the only way species become incorporated into a trend. But that isn’t the point. The point is that this rendering of PE “saves the phenomenon” at the center of Gould’s early vision for evolutionary paleontology—improvement in the basic design of a large taxon. And this supplies a satisfying answer to the question posed above: how did Gould weather the publication of PE with his basic view of evolution mostly intact?
* * *
I titled this essay “Paradox of Stasis” because there is something superficially paradoxical about the stability of Gould’s thinking between 1970 and 1975.* A naïve observer, confronted with evidence of Gould’s adaptationism and progressivism, might understandably look to PE as a kind of heel turn. Sure, before PE Gould said some pretty un-Gould-y things about evolution. But after 1972 things must have clicked into place. —Right?
Wrong. PE did not mark a sea change in Gould’s thought, despite the important role it would come to play in his mature view of life. The reason is that PE, and especially the critical section on trends, was entirely compatible with his youthful view of evolution. It was only after 1975 that the tide began to shift for various reasons to be explored in the next and final part of this essay. As a result, PE would be thrust into the center of Gould’s renewed campaign to establish paleontology as an essential and irreducible contributor to evolutionary theory.
[* The expression “paradox of stasis” also has a meaning in the paleontological literature. Here is a nice philosophical treatment by Jonathan Kaplan, and check out this old post by Derek Turner.]
References
Dresow, M. 2019. Macroevolution evolving: punctuated equilibria and the roots of Stephen Jay Gould’s second macroevolutionary synthesis. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Science, 75:15–23. [This is a sequel to the paper cited in the previous part of this essay as Dresow (2017)]
Eldredge, N. and Gould, S.J. 1972. Punctuated equilibria: an alternative to phyletic gradualism. In T.J.M. Schopf (Ed.), Models in Paleobiology, pp. 82–115. San Francisco: Cooper & Co.
Gould, S.J. 1977. Eternal metaphors in paleontology. In A. Hallam (Ed.). Patterns of Evolution as Illustrated by the Fossil Record, pp. 1–26. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Gould, S.J. 2002. The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Gould, S.J. and Eldredge, N. 1977. Punctuated equilibria: the tempo and mode of evolution reconsidered. Paleobiology 3:115–151.
Huxley, J. 1942. Evolution: The Modern Synthesis. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Mayr, E. 1954. Change of genetic environment and evolution. In J. Huxley, A.C. Hardy, E.B. Ford (Eds.), Evolution as a Process, pp. 157–180. London: Gorge Allen & Unwin Ltd.
Schaeffer, B. 1965. The role of experimentation in the origin of higher levels of organization. Systematic Zoology 14:318–336.
Sepkoski, D. 2012. Rereading the Fossil Record: The Growth of Paleobiology as an Evolutionary Discipline. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Simpson, G.G. 1944. Tempo and Mode in Evolution. New York: Columbia University Press.